Intended for healthcare professionals

Commentary

test of capacity has little practical benefit

BMJ 2005; 331 doi: https://doi.org/10.1136/bmj.331.7530.1469 (Published 15 December 2005) Cite this as: BMJ 2005;331:1469
  1. Derek Chiswick, consultant forensic psychiatrist (derek.chiswick{at}dial.pipex.com)1
  1. 1 Orchard Clinic, Royal Edinburgh Hospital, Edinburgh EH10 5HF

    In a civilised society mental health laws protect insight-less seriously mentally ill people from themselves and protect citizens from the actions of those who are seriously mentally ill. These principles have been the cornerstone of mental health law for 50 years. But legislation must be fit for today. It should embrace contemporary concern for patient autonomy but at the same time deliver what society requires of it. Should decision making capacity have a place in modern mental health law?1 Of course it should. Should capacity be the over-riding factor that trumps all other considerations as it does with physical illness? That goes too far.

    Capacity has not earned this pivotal status in routine clinical psychiatry for four reasons: it is a poorly defined concept; it is consequently difficult to assess; its assessment adds little of practical benefit when considering the clinical grounds for compulsory treatment; and its alleged presence will be used as a convenient device to legitimise rejection and delay in the treatment of mentally ill patients.

    Definition and assessment

    Capacity is a shaky concept in psychiatry. Scottish legislators opted instead for “decision making ability.”2 It is difficult to distinguish the two, and indeed, “similar factors will be taken into account” when assessing both of them.3 Decision making ability, we are told, is in the mind whereas capacity is a function of the brain. Both depend on the ability to understand, reason, make an informed choice, and communicate. We do not have a “metacognoscope,” and we must therefore rely on clinical judgment and research schedules. Researchers are pretty good at agreeing whether capacity is present.4 But an assessment of capacity alone will not tell the clinician whether any particular patient should be detained for treatment.

    Capacity is a fluctuating commodity. The state of mind of a patient is often ambiguous; patients may apparently resist treatment but hope that someone will intervene. Capacity varies over time and in degree. It is easier to assess capacity in people with a chronic but stable condition such as a learning disability or dementia than in those with an acute mental illness, in which fluctuations in capacity are the rule rather than the exception. Comparisons with physical illness are stretched as psychiatric treatments tend to be much more complex than single surgical treatments. Is it possible to assess a patient's capacity separately for use of an antipsychotic, an antidepressant, and a mood stabiliser?

    What does capacity add?

    Doyal and Sheather cite with approval recent Scottish legislation implemented in October 2005.1 The Scottish Act has five criteria for a compulsory treatment order, all of which must be present (box).

    It is difficult, if not impossible, to see what the test of decision making adds to the other four criteria. If a mentally disordered patient is deemed a serious risk to self or others, if treatment is available, and if the patient refuses voluntary treatment because he or she lacks insight, how will consideration of capacity affect the clinical decision to treat? For example, what useful information does an assessment of capacity tell us about three patients who have, respectively, jumped from a third floor apartment window to flee persecutory hallucinations; been evicted from accommodation after sawing through domestic gas pipes to counter atmospheric pollution; and given a display of naked gymnastics to children in the street while under the conviction of being an athlete of Olympic standard. All gave what was for them a persuasive reason for the appropriateness of their behaviour, an acknowledgment that others might find it peculiar, a conviction that it was based on reality, and a determination to avoid being seen as mentally ill. They were all opposed to compulsory psychiatric treatment.

    How do they fare with the components of decision making? They understood perfectly an explanation that they were mentally ill but did not accept it; they fully appreciated the importance of information given to them, but they reasoned that treatment would be harmful. They expressed a choice to have no treatment, even if it left them homeless. Do they have capacity? I do not know. However, their lack of insight into a dangerous, harmful mental illness makes compulsory treatment appropriate. Whether they have capacity is an entirely academic consideration; it is neither measurable nor relevant.

    Five criteria for Scottish compulsory treatment order

    • A mental disorder

    • Medical treatment that will alleviate or prevent worsening

    • Significant risk to self or others

    • Significantly impaired ability to make decisions about treatment

    • Necessity of making the order

    Rejection

    Supposing these patients were also known to be difficult to treat because of histories of substance misuse and previous violence when in hospital. A capacity test gives an over-stretched and reluctant mental health service an opportunity to reject the patient and passively facilitate entry to the criminal justice system. Indeed Doyal and Sheather recommend that mentally ill people who threaten others but are believed to retain capacity should be referred to the police.1 They do not say if, how, or where treatment for these people should be provided.

    Conclusion

    Patient autonomy is of the utmost importance in medical practice. But it is a fact of life that detained psychiatric patients lose autonomy. This is why the whole process of compulsory detention must be governed by sophisticated legislation that provides for scrutiny by independent statutory bodies. Crucial decisions about compulsory treatment cannot turn solely on an assessment of capacity. A capacity test will lead to delay or rejection in doctors' implementation of compulsory measures of care. Is (self inflicted) death with human rights preserved a more desirable outcome than compulsory treatment?

    Footnotes

    • ARTICLE
    • Competing interests DC is a medical member of the Mental Health Tribunal for Scotland.

    References

    1. 1.
    2. 2.
    3. 3.
    4. 4.
    View Abstract

    Log in

    Log in through your institution

    Subscribe

    * For online subscription